A project of the Tennessee Fair Housing Council

NFHAO Home | about NFHAO | forums | contact us
search:  
search Legal Research Articles only
go to advanced search  < 
search help  < 
News Archive
Old Headlines
Press Releases
Print Advocate
Action Alerts
 
Resources
Get Help Near You
Events
Job Listings
Links
Book Club
Sponsors
 
Discussion
Message Forums
The Guest Room
 
Legal Research
Case Database
Recovery Database
HUD Settlements
Statutes and Regs
Articles
HUD Resources
 
Home > Legal Research > Legal Research Articles


Justin D. Cummins *
Copyright (c) 1998 Howard Law Journal

Cite as: 41 How. L.J. 455

(reprinted by permission)


Spring, 1998

"You cannot get rid of the subordination without eliminating the privilege as well." 1

INTRODUCTION

In recent years, several analytical disciplines, including late modern and postmodern philosophy, 2 critical race theory and feminist jurisprudence, 3 and social psychology 4 have begun to acknowledge that the self is multiple. 5 This insight cuts to the core of not only how we understand ourselves individually and collectively, but also how we should regulate human affairs through the law. Until now, the classical liberal or modernist notion of the self as singular has dominated our thinking, particularly in the legal arena. 6 The modernist concept of the self as unitary and independent of experience is inaccurate, however, and continues to thwart the project of eliminating discrimination in the United States. 7

To show the descriptive and prescriptive inadequacy of the modernist notion of the self, this article draws primarily on critical race theory and social psychology. The analysis starts from the position that discrimination takes two main forms: conscious and unconscious. 8 Even though the ensuing analysis can be applied to various bases of discrimination - such as gender, socioeconomic status, sexual orientation, and physical ability - this article will focus on racial discrimination for the sake of clarity.

Recognizing that the self is multiple and relational has several important implications for the law. First, it enables litigators and courts to refashion the disparate treatment doctrine 9 to remedy currently unaddressed discrimination. 10 Second, this more accurate understanding of the self enables litigators and courts to reconceive the disparate impact doctrine 11 to identify and address discrimination in all forms. 12 Third, and most significantly, embracing this notion of self makes anti-discrimination law transformative, a mechanism for vindicating - in the most meaningful sense - the principles enshrined in the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments to the United States Constitution. 13

I. CURRENT ANTI-DISCRIMINATION LAW: THE UNITARY SELF, "INTENTIONAL" AND "PARTICULARIZED" RACISM, AND FORMAL EQUALITY

In spite of the persuasiveness of arguments that the self is fractured, United States jurisprudence remains mired in the morass of classical liberal or modernist thought. 14 According to modernists, the self is one-dimensional and formed prior to experience. 15 From this perspective, there can be only one state of consciousness or level of volition, such that if one does not consciously discriminate, no illicit actions or legally cognizable harm occur. 16 This analytical stance also hinges on the flawed presumption that conduct flows only from individual, independent actors based on clearly identifiable motives; there is little recognition of the role of societal attitudes or action and hidden or mixed motives. 17 Consequently, anti-discrimination jurisprudence addresses only certain types of discrimination, and what little discrimination it does address, it does to a reprehensibly limited extent.

A. The Disparate Treatment Doctrine Under the Illusion of a Unitary Self

Anti-discrimination law remains woefully inadequate because, in accordance with the disparate treatment doctrine, it only recognizes conscious acts of discrimination and considers only conduct directly attributable to specific and independent actors. 18 In other words, the requirements of "intentional" and "particularized" discrimination mean that the disparate treatment doctrine permits unconscious discrimination and discrimination flowing from institutional or societal forces to flourish. In this area of the law, then, United States jurisprudence has lost the proverbial forest for the trees.

1. An Inequitable Requirement of "Intent"

 

Current anti-discrimination law requires a showing of "intent" - conscious and deliberate discrimination - in order for a defendant to be found liable. 19 This standard, which flows directly from the assumption that the self is unitary, poses a major problem. The "intent" requirement places an extremely heavy burden on plaintiffs, 20 meaning a significant amount of discrimination, especially of the unconscious variety, persists unchecked. 21

The unconscionability of this evidentiary imposition becomes even more apparent once one realizes that the burden falls on members of groups that typically have less resources, representation, and power. 22 The problem with this evidentiary burden, however, goes beyond the virtual impossibility of proving unconscious discrimination under the "intent" standard. Even in circumstances where conscious discrimination exists, discriminatory intent can be easily concealed. 23 Moreover, because behavior usually results from a variety of motives, defendants can often plausibly, in the legal sense, allege that racially neutral considerations underlay their actions. 24 Furthermore, discrimination often involves several decision makers, making it that much more difficult to pinpoint an explicit discriminatory motive. 25

The seminal case setting forth the "intent" requirement, Washington v. Davis, 26 illustrates the major problem with an analytical approach premised on the unitariness of the self. In Davis, two unsuccessful African-American candidates for the District of Columbia Metropolitan Police Department alleged racial discrimination in the Department's hiring practices. The plaintiffs asserted that Test 21, a written exam administered to test verbal ability and reading comprehension of job applicants, discriminated against African Americans.

Although the United States Supreme Court ruled against the plaintiffs, it admitted that there was no proof that Test 21 scores predicted job performance or measured success in job-related training. 27 Put simply, the Court recognized that the exam had little practical value. Moreover, the Court acknowledged that African Americans failed Test 21 at four times the rate of whites. 28 Nonetheless, the Court held that the test did not violate the law because no express "intent" to discriminate had been shown. 29 The Court argued that the Department's justification for the use of Test 21 - to upgrade the communication skills of the city's police officers - provided a lawful basis for the exam. 30 To so hold, after admitting that the only meaningful consequence of using Test 21 was the exclusion of African Americans, the Court had to disregard the likelihood that unconscious discrimination underlay the administering of the test. The Court made this analytical error because it started from the flawed premise that the self is unitary and incapable of having unacknowledged motives, discriminatory or otherwise. 31

2. An Unreasonable Standard of "Particularized" Discrimination

The concept of a unitary self, which underlies the disparate treatment doctrine creates another significant problem for those seeking to eliminate discrimination and achieve substantive equality 32 through litigation. It unduly narrows the scope of agency, so that many types of discriminatory acts fall outside the purview of anti-discrimination law. In a legal framework premised on the existence of an unchanging and autonomous self, only individual actors can be held liable for discrimination, and then only if they affirmatively choose to engage in specific conduct that courts deem discriminatory. From this perspective, it is not possible to discriminate simply by participating in human affairs as they are or, otherwise stated, to discriminate passively; one must actively decide to depart from the supposedly race-neutral status quo. 33 In other words, agency is individually, rather than intersubjectively or societally, formed and executed. 34

Given the pervasiveness of group-based and institutional discrimination regarding housing, employment, education, health care, lend ing, and other components of the opportunity structure, 35 the existing disparate treatment doctrine does not suffice. In order to obtain a legal remedy under current law, a plaintiff must identify an individualized culprit and prove that this actor affirmatively committed the precise discriminatory act(s) that inflicted the harm(s) alleged. 36 Such requirements mean a large amount of discrimination, especially of a passive or societal nature, goes unacknowledged and unaddressed by courts.

Village of Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Development Corporation 37 demonstrates the difficulties of establishing culpable agency when a unitary and rigid concept of the self undergirds the analysis. In Arlington Heights, a nonprofit development corporation acquired a purchase option on land on which it intended to build a racially and socioeconomically integrated townhouse project. The developer planned to build the housing project in a suburb of Chicago, Arlington Heights, which had an African-American population of approximately 25% at the time of the lawsuit. 38 Prior to this development proposal, Arlington Heights bodies had zoned the contemplated site of affordable housing for only single-family homes. Thus, the housing developer petitioned Arlington Heights to rezone the area to permit multi-family housing. 39

Following the recommendations of the planning commission, the Arlington Heights Board of Trustees rejected the rezoning application, alleging that the protection of property values and the preservation of the municipal zoning scheme required such action. 40 In reality, as the lower court record reflected, much of the opposition to the affordable housing project related to concern over the possible influx of people of color. 41 The United States Supreme Court considered this evidence and even admitted that opponents of the housing development "might have been motivated by opposition to minority groups." 42 Nonetheless, the Court held that Arlington Heights and its residents did not violate the law when they prevented the construction of the housing project. 43

In order to reach such an illogical conclusion, the Court had to conclude that the defendants did not choose to engage in any behavior that could be construed as discriminatory. The defendants were, according to the Court, merely seeking to preserve the zoning scheme and protect property values. 44 Such reasoning only becomes plausible if one presumes the self to be autonomous and static. In other words, the Court had to assume that the racist attitudes permeating society did not affect the self or alter the nature of its actions. 45 If, on the other hand, the Court had viewed the self as fluid and experientially shaped, it could have recognized that even "race-neutral" acts amount to racial discrimination when the individual and collective psyche have been tainted by racism. 46 Otherwise stated, merely maintaining the status quo, in this case by preserving the zoning scheme, in a racist society rises to the level of discriminatory conduct, even if the defendants had no conscious or unconscious discriminatory intent.

A brief reflection from a common-sense perspective confirms the truthfulness of this point. Decades of discrimination against people of color have resulted in fewer resources and choices for people of color. 47 Because people of color have comparatively less resources and wealth, they are disproportionately limited to living in low- or moderate-income housing. 48 Therefore, the prohibition of less-expensive housing by a municipality such as Arlington Heights perpetuates the exclusion of people of color from more desirable housing and other aspects of the opportunity structure. 49

To verify that discrimination dictated the defendants' conduct in Arlington Heights, one need look no further than the second rationalization for the denial of the zoning variance: the protection of property values. This justification rests solely on the flawed premise that the presence of people of color, especially those of low- or moderate-incomes, will automatically drive down real estate values. This fear has absolutely no basis in fact. 50 Thus, no credible explanation exists for excluding integrated housing except racist stereotyping of people of color as criminally inclined, irresponsible, or otherwise inferior. 51 The Court could not consider the defendants' conduct discriminatory, however, because the Court's view of the self as independent of experience and unchanging prevented it from seeing the role of societal racism in coloring the defendants' actions. 52

B. The Consequences of the Existing Disparate Treatment Doctrine: The Legitimation of Discrimination and the Perpetuation of Racial Hierarchy

As the discussed above, both the "intent" and "particularized" discrimination requirements imposed by the disparate treatment doctrine allow a substantial amount of discrimination to continue unremedied. 53 This should not be a surprise, especially in view of the structural flaw of current anti-discrimination law. Anti-discrimination law, as reflected by the disparate treatment doctrine, only seeks to secure formal equality 54 or "race-neutrality." Because the larger social, political, and economic structures remain racialized, formally equal treatment under "race-neutral" laws merely reproduces the racialized and discriminatory arrangements in the larger world. 55 Worse still, this discrimination and accompanying racial inequality take on an air of appropriateness and naturalness because, as the popular sentiment goes, "if it were actually discriminatory conduct, the law would address it." 56 In other words, having anti-discrimination laws, even as inadequate as they are, creates the impression that as long as the courts enforce the laws, no discrimination will occur. Therefore, the presence of anti-discrimination laws manufactures a sense of legitimacy for the legal and, by implication, the political, economic, and social status quo. 57

The legitimation of "unintentional" and "societal" discrimination means that members of the power structure can appear reasonable when attributing the negative consequences of racial subordination to the personal failings of people of color rather than to the true causes. 58 The negative outgrowths of discrimination, then, become an ex post facto justification for the past discrimination against people of color and the favoring of whites. 59 Similarly, the current social, economic, and institutional challenges faced by people of color due to past and present discrimination become a "rational basis" for discrimination in the future, perpetuating the simultaneous subordination of people of color and privilege of whites. 60 Consequently, anti-discrimination law, as dictated by the disparate treatment doctrine, ultimately ensures the continuation of racial hierarchy and precludes the realization of substantive equality. 61

II. MEANINGFUL ANTI-DISCRIMINATION LAW: THE MULTIPLE SELF, UNCONSCIOUS AND INSTITUTIONAL RACISM, AND SUBSTANTIVE EQUALITY

In order to eradicate discrimination from our institutions and society, anti-discrimination law must be informed by the insight that the self is relational, changing, and fractured. 62 What this understanding of the self means in concrete terms can be shown by the example of a hypothetical African-American woman who is lesbian and low-income. The notion of a non-unitary self embodies the recognition that this hypothetical person has distinct, but often interwoven, circumstances and realities based on being African-American, female, homosexual, and low-income. 63 In addition, this person interprets and is affected by the same phenomena differently if, in the particular context, the phenomena are experienced as an African American, as a woman, as a lesbian, or as one with little capital, or as a combination of these constructed traits. 64

While the preceding example may be extreme in that all of the traits ascribed to the hypothetical person are bases for discrimination and subordination, one should not lose sight of the fact that a white, male, heterosexual, financially wealthy person also has varied realities, multiple identities, and a fractured self. 65 The major difference is that the former person is subordinated and the latter person is privileged in the United States based on their respective, socially constructed traits. Obviously the categories assigned to either hypothetical person, and to people generally, are not fixed, clear-cut, or all-inclusive. 66 Moreover, the two hypothetical people, like every one, often experience phenomena, interact, and understand the world from more than one vantage point. 67 In short, identity and the self are multiple for every one of us. 68

A. The Disparate Treatment Doctrine in Light of the Fractured Self

This new conception of the self has important implications for the disparate treatment doctrine. The insight that the self is non-unitary canal open up litigators and courts, thinking about what it means to have discriminatory intent and agency and what constitutes a legitimate legal theory for bringing a discrimination lawsuit.

1. The Expansion of Legal Culpability

Legal analysis, guided by an understanding of the self as non-unitary and relational, will correct deficiencies endemic in anti-discrimination law. First, the disparate treatment doctrine can now recognize that racism and discrimination infect the unconscious as well as the conscious. 69 Second, a reconceptualized disparate treatment doctrine can define discriminatory agency in a manner that identifies fully, and addresses effectively, discriminatory conduct. 70

a. A More Accurate Concept of Intent

While there remains some disagreement within the psychological community as to the reasons for, and functions of, the unconscious, 71 nearly all experts agree that the unconscious exists and plays a powerful role in shaping human behavior. 72 Because unconscious racism and discrimination occur, 73 the question becomes how litigators and courts can identify when unconscious discrimination underlies the conduct at issue in a lawsuit. The adoption of a more comprehensive and equitable intent standard provides one response. This new intent requirement would necessitate a contextualized and nuanced analysis by courts. In each case, the courts should consider whether the alleged discriminatory conduct conveys a symbolic message to which our society attaches racial significance. 74 The determination that society views the alleged differential treatment in racial terms would constitute a finding that the defendants' conduct flowed from racially discriminatory intent. 75

Reconsidering Davis, in light of the non-unitariness of the self, should make this new analytical approach more concrete. After reflecting on this country's history and current circumstances, the Court would discern that, in two respects, society ascribes racial significance to the administering of Test 21 to prospective police officers.

First, the demand to demonstrate "proficiency" in verbal and written language skills harkens back to the racial "science" of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. 76 This racist pseudo-science purported to prove the inherent inferiority of African Americans, especially in terms of language skills and intelligence. 77 The myth of racial inferiority legitimated and perpetuated by racial "science" continues to this day, as illustrated by the persistence of social scientific work that claims to prove the superior intelligence of whites. 78 In this context, the administering of a verbal and language skills exam takes on a decidedly racialized character.

Second, the job position of law enforcement officer, for which officials administered Test 21, historically has been off limits to people of color, especially African Americans. 79 Because police officers have a position of authority and power that people of color traditionally have not had in the United States, the ongoing exclusion of African Americans from the police force has racial meaning. 80 The facts of Davis underscore this point. The African-American plaintiffs sought to join the Washington, D.C. force, which polices a predominantly African-American city. 81 If the Court were to adopt an intent standard that recognized unconscious volition and undertook the foregoing analysis, it would conclude that the defendants violated the law by administering Test 21.

b. A More Comprehensive Notion of Agency

Understanding the self as relational, changing, and multiple will enable litigators and courts to discern and remedy of discriminatory agency in all of its manifestations. In other words, they will realize that the self, and therefore individual actors, are shaped by experience and interaction with others and the overarching environment. 82 Consequently, litigators and courts can recognize that conduct, even if not motivated by a conscious or unconscious intent to discriminate, nonetheless amounts to discrimination if it perpetuates a status quo that flows from institutional or societal racism. 83 One critical race theorist succinctly described the role of societal racism in creating culpable agency among individuals that engage in "race-neutral" conduct: "the actors themselves are part of a culture and presumably could not have acted without being influenced by racial considerations, even if they were unaware of their racist beliefs." 84

A brief discussion of Arlington Heights will illustrate this refashioned concept of agency and the analytical implications. In that case, the defendants denied a zoning variance that would have allowed for the construction of racially integrated, affordable housing on the grounds that the municipal zoning scheme should be preserved and property values protected. 85 While these reasons are facially "race- neutral," they perpetuate a status quo that directly grows out of systematic discrimination at the institutional and societal levels. 86 To date, racism in various forms has distorted the housing market to the detriment of people of color. 87 Local zoning schemes have been one of the most pervasive and effective means of exclusion. 88 In this context, maintenance of the Arlington Heights' zoning scheme takes on a racially discriminatory hue.

Similarly, the property-values justification flows from institutional and societal discrimination. 89 Predominantly white suburbs, such as Arlington Heights, have high property values precisely because central city communities of color do not. 90 Throughout the twentieth century, public and private policies have concentrated poverty in certain areas and wealth in others through racial discrimination with respect to housing, education, employment, lending, and so forth. 91 Therefore, Arlington Heights' privileged position reflects past and present racial discrimination; the maintenance of that privileged position, as reflected by artificially high property values, consequently amounts to discriminatory agency.

2. The Disparate Impact Doctrine Refashioned in Light of the Relational Self

The reconceptualized intent and agency standards explored above would undoubtedly increase the opportunities for plaintiffs to litigate discrimination claims - and prevail. Acknowledgment of the non-unitariness of the self, however, would enhance the potency of anti-discrimination law litigation in another way completely independent of the expansion of the intent and agency concepts. A proper understanding of the self would provide the theoretical foundation for a new cause of action, that which shall be referred to as the disproportionate impact doctrine. Disproportionate impact theory closely resembles disparate impact theory, but it addresses both sides of the equation, so to speak. In other words, while disparate impact theory offers a remedy only for racial subordination, 92 disproportionate impact theory would provide a remedy for either racial subordination or racial privilege. 93 For example, if whites receive benefits - jobs, promotions, contracts, housing opportunities, or loans - to an extent substantially exceeding their numbers within the pool of prospective recipients or applicants, people of color would have the evidentiary basis for a cause of action. 94

Disproportionate impact theory hinges on the insight that the self is dynamic and interdependent and, consequently, that the privileging of one means the subordination of another (and vice-versa). 95 When using this analytical approach, courts must vigorously guard against the conceptual error made regarding affirmative action and voting rights - equating rigid neutrality or symmetry with fairness. 96 To put it more concretely, disproportionate benefits to people of color may be appropriate in some cases, such as when the differential results from the effort to remedy the effects of past or ongoing discrimination. Given whites' historical and current position of privilege, however, it is highly unlikely that disproportionate benefits to them would be appropriate in the immediate future. 97

Courts must always undertake this contextualized and nuanced analysis or the disproportionate impact doctrine will become yet an other tool for claimants of "reverse discrimination" to defend white privilege and rationalize racial subordination. 98

A brief discussion of Smith v. Western Electric Co., Inc. 99 will help to explicate the disproportionate impact doctrine. In Smith, six African-American employees filed a class-action lawsuit, asserting that the defendant employer had racially discriminated against African Americans concerning hiring, promotion, and other terms and conditions of employment. In ruling against the plaintiffs, the court disregarded the clear disproportionate privileging of whites and the accompanying discrimination against people of color with respect to hiring: the employer hired more than 20% of white applicants, but less than 10% of African-American applicants. 100 The court argued that these statistics did not take into account applicants' performance on the admission test given by the employer. 101 According to the court's purportedly race-neutral analysis, white and African-American applicants who performed well on the test were hired by the defendant at approximately the same rate. 102

Contrary to the court's assertions, the test used in Smith, much like Test 21 at issue in Davis, was not a neutral mechanism for evaluating job applicants. In reality, white applicants received a high score on the test, and thus were more seriously considered for employment, in disproportionate numbers. 103 Consequently, the administering of the test created and perpetuated white privilege. 104 That there was such an impact becomes even more troubling in light of the fact that performance on the test had a "low correlation with job success." 105 In other words, like Test 21 in Davis, the admission test used in Smith had little practical significance beyond its disproportionate racial impact. Nonetheless, the employer continued to use the test as the primary basis for making hiring decisions. 106 Despite such compelling evidence of racial discrimination, the court in Smith could not find the employer liable. The existing disparate impact doctrine did not allow the court to consider whether the test disproportionately privileged white applicants and, therefore, discriminated against applicants of color.

A short examination of the court's analysis in Smith regarding the plaintiffs' discriminatory promotion claim further illustrates the application of the disproportionate impact doctrine. The court concluded that the employer did not discriminate against African-American employees concerning promotions because African-American employees typically had less specialized skills and, thus, were less promotable. 107 This analysis ignored the disproportionate privileging of white employees, paradoxically, even as the analysis acknowledged it. Otherwise stated, the court admitted that white employees were better positioned concerning promotions without critically examining why that was so. The court did not undertake such an examination because the current disparate impact doctrine only permits an inquiry into whether there was a legally cognizable adverse impact on African Americans.

Had the court in Smith employed the disproportionate impact doctrine, it could have considered all evidence of racial discrimination, including the disproportionate privileging of white employees. For example, the court could have recognized the significance of the fact that the supervisors charged with promoting employees were white and were channeling the work that imparted specialized skills to fellow white employees. 108 This channeling often prevented African- American employees from being eligible for promotions because they did not have the chance to develop specialized skills. 109 If the court's analysis in Smith had turned on these facts, the court could not have plausibly relied on the lack-of-skills argument to explain away the disproportionate advantage bestowed on white employees regarding promotions. In short, the court would have recognized that white employees were more promotable precisely because of the racial discrimination engaged in by their employer.

B. Reconceptualizing the Disparate Treatment and Disparate Impact Doctrines to Eliminate Racial Discrimination and Dismante Racial Hierarchy

As illustrated above, anti-discrimination law reconceived in light of the non-unitary nature of the self would address all forms of discrimination. Expanding the definition of intent and the scope of agency would enable courts to remedy unconscious and societal discrimination, respectively. Moreover, addressing racial (white) privilege in addition to racial subordination under a disproportionate impact theory, would empower courts to identify and remedy still more discrimination because racial discrimination can manifest itself as either privilege or subordination, not just subordination. 110

By exposing and addressing the twin effects of discrimination (the privilege of whites and the subordination of people of color), refashioned anti-discrimination law would help to remove the sense of neutrality, naturalness, and inevitability that has attached to racial exclusion and inequality to date. 111 Removal of the aura of legitimacy of racial exclusion and inequality would make possible, even inevitable, greater participation by people of color in the opportunity structure; by so doing, antidiscrimination law could pave the way for dismantling racial hierarchy. 112 With the project of destroying racial hierarchy underway, the realization of substantive equality for everyone would certainly follow. 113

CONCLUSION

The philosophical debate about whether the self is unitary or non-unitary has serious implications for the law. As anti-discrimination law exemplifies, legal analysis premised on a unitary nature of the self greatly undermines the effectiveness of legal rules and mechanisms. In the context of anti-discrimination law, a unitary-based analysis fails to address unconscious and societal discrimination. Not only does anti-discrimination law fail to remedy adequately racial subordination, it also completely ignores racial (white) privilege, all in the quest to preserve formal equality. Consequently, anti-discrimination law, as dictated by the current disparate treatment and disparate impact doctrines, preserves the racial status quo.

In contrast, basing anti-discrimination law on the understanding that the self is not unitary would have several positive effects. Anti- discrimination law, so conceived, would enable litigators and courts to use the disparate treatment doctrine to address all discrimination, whether conscious or unconscious. In addition, this analytical approach will expose and root out the subtle types of discrimination that perpetuate a status quo tainted by institutional racism. Finally, the more accurate notion of the self would allow litigators and courts to refashion the disparate impact doctrine to unmask and address both subordination and privilege. The net effect will be the elimination of not only racial discrimination, but also racial hierarchy. Nothing less will achieve that which the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments demand.


NOTES


* J.D. 1997, University of Minnesota Law School; M.A. 1996, Hubert H. Humphrey Institute of Public Affairs; B.A. 1992, Haverford College. S.T.P. The author is currently a civil rights lawyer based in Minneapolis, Minnesota.

n1 Trina Grillo, Anti-Essentialism and Intersectionality: Tools to Dismantle the Master's House, 10 Berkeley Women's L.J. 16, 19 (1995).

n2 The postmodernists are perhaps the most well-known proponents of the view that the self is non-unitary rather than unitary. In deconstructing the self, however, the postmodernists typically do not offer a positive alternative concept. See, e.g., Deconstruction in a Nutshell: A Conversation with Jaques Derrida 113-21 (John D. Caputo ed., 1997); Ian Hacking, Self- Improvement, in Foucault: A Critical Reader 235-49 (David Couzens Hoy ed., 1992); Hubert L. Dreyfus & Paul Rabinow, Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics 208-26 (1983). The late modernists offer a more helpful view of the self because they try to reconstruct the world and individual and communal relations, avoiding the nihilism that often underlies the postmodernist vision. See generally Selya Benhabib, Situating the Self: Gender Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics (1992); Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (1982). Non-western philosophers, such as thinkers within the Buddhist tradition, also have articulated a compelling concept of the self as multiple. See generally Anne Carolyn Klein, Meeting the Great Bliss Queen: Buddhists, Feminists, and the Art of the Self (1995).

n3 For accounts that weave together the insights of both critical race theory and feminist theory when describing the fractured self, see Regina Austin, "Sapphire Bound," 1989 Wis. L. Rev. 539; Kimberle Williams Crenshaw, Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence Against Women of Color, 43 Stan. L. Rev. 1241 (1993); Grillo, supra note 1; Angela P. Harris, Foreword: The Unbearable Lightness of Identity, 11 Berkeley Women's L.J. 207 (1996).

n4 See, e.g., 19 Sigmund Freud, The Ego and the Id, in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud 3 (James Strachey ed., 1961); Richard E. Nisbett & Timothy DeCamp Wilson, Telling More than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes, 84 Psychol. Rev. 231 (1977).

n5 The fractured nature of the self results from the diversity of experiences that characterize modern-day existence. See generally Kenneth J. Gergen, The Saturated Self: Dilemmas of Identity in Contemporary Life (1991) (describing the interaction of the multi- faceted self with the larger world). The fractured self interprets and is shaped by later experiences, including interaction and conflict with other components of the self. See generally James Boyle, Is Subjectivity Possible? The Postmodern Subject in Legal Theory, 62 U. Colo. L. Rev. 489 (1991) (discussing the internal tensions within the self).

n6 See, e.g., Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U.S. 200 (1995) (holding that, in awarding construction contracts, all racial classifications, whether imposed by federal, state, or local governments, shall be subjected to strict judicial scrutiny); Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630 (1993) (finding a redistribution scheme designed to enhance the voting strength of communities of color to be unconstitutional); Wards Cove Packing Co., Inc. v. Antonio, 490 U.S. 642 (1989) (ruling that a substantial racial imbalance in the work force was irrelevant to an inquiry into the existence of discrimination); Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229 (1976) (holding that the racially disparate impact of a test administered to prospective employees did not violate the law absent a showing of discriminatory intent).

n7 Alan Freeman, Antidiscrimiantion Law: The View from 1989, in The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critiques 121-41 (David Kairys ed., 1990).

n8 For a detailed analysis of unconscious discrimination in the legal context, see Charles R. Lawrence III, The Id, the Ego, and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism, 39 Stan. L. Rev. 317, 329-43 (1987).

n9 The current disparate treatment doctrine prohibits "intentional" differential treatment on the basis of race or other perceived traits. See generally Joel Friedman & George Strickler, The Law of Entertainment Discrimination: Cases and Materials (3d ed. 1987).

n10 See infra notes 61-91 and accompanying text.

n11 This standard does not require a showing of discriminatory "intent" on the part of the defendant(s) for a plaintiff to prevail. Instead, a plaintiff need only show that the existing policies or practices have had a substantially adverse effect on members of a protected class and defendant does not make a showing of a sufficient business justification. See generally Robert G. Schwemm, Housing Discrimination: Law and Litigation (1990).

n12 See infra notes 92-109 and accompanying text.

n13 U.S. Const. amend. V, XIV. These amendments protect against federal, state, and local governmental impingement on the equality of any person because of, inter alia, race. The Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments also protect against discrimination by private actors where "state action" has been found or where the private actor has engaged in an activity traditionally performed by the government, see, e.g., Marsh v. Alabama, 326 U.S. 501 (1946) (holding that a town wholly owned by a corporation was like any other town and its operation was, therefore, a "public function" amounting to "state action"), or a symbiotic relationship exists between the government and the private discriminator, see, e.g., Burton v. Wilmington Parking Auth., 365 U.S. 715 (1961) (holding that the mutually beneficial relationship between the state and private discriminator triggered "state action" analysis).

n14 See, e.g., Hunter v. Underwood, 471 U.S. 222 (1985) (holding that Section 182 of the Alabama Constitution violated the Fourteenth Amendment after finding the presence of clear discriminatory "intent"); Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229 (1976) (reasoning that a showing of discriminatory "intent" is necessary to trigger legal culpability). This anachronistic perspective holds that the self is not interdependent and experientially created and shaped. See generally John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1971) (outlining an analytical approach - decision-making behind "the veil of ignorance" - to forge a more just society).

n15 See, e.g., Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason 154 (Norman Kemp Smith trans., 1958).

n16 See, e.g., Hunter, 471 U.S. at 222; Davis, 426 U.S. at 229.

n17 See, e.g., Village of Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Hous. Dev. Corp., 429 U.S. 252 (1977) (holding that racially discriminatory intent must be proven to establish a violation of the Fourteenth Amendment; a racially disparate impact is insufficient to show a constitutional violation has occurred).

n18 Id.; Davis, 426 U.S. at 229. The United States Supreme Court's recent decisions regarding race conscious remedies for past racial discrimination, such as affirmative action and voting district reapportionment, also offer graphic examples of the Court's self-imposed blindness to anything but "intentional" and "clearly identifiable and attributable" racial discrimination. See, e.g., Adarand Constructors, Inc., 515 U.S. at 200; Shaw, 509 U.S. at 630.

n19 For the first articulation of this proposition, see Davis, 426 U.S. at 229.

n20 For an incisive articulation of this predicament, see generally John Hart Ely, The Centrality and Limits of Motivation Analysis, 15 San Diego L. Rev. 1155, 1160 (1978) and Kenneth Karst, The Costs of Motive-Centered Inquiry, 15 San Diego L. Rev. 1163, 1165 (1978). See also John Charles Boger, Toward Ending Residential Segregation: A Fair Share Proposal for the Next Reconstruction, 71 N.C. L. Rev. 1574, 1583-84 (1993) (discussing the difficulty of showing that a claimant has suffered a legally cognizable injury even under the more plaintiff-friendly disparate impact standard); Lawrence, supra note 8, at 369-76 (exploring strategies to overcome the substantial evidentiary burdens imposed by the "intent" standard).

n21 Id.

n22 People of color, the typical victims of invidious racial discrimination in the United States, usually have less wealth, access to resources, and political power. Melvin Oliver & Thomas Shapiro, Black Wealth/White Wealth: A New Perspective on Racial Inequality 136-151 (1995) (detailing the discrimination-induced dearth of resources in communities of color in the United States); Michael Omi & Howard Winant, Racial Formation in the United States: From the 1960s to the 1990s 66 (2d ed., 1994) (observing that throughout United States history, people of color have been excluded from critical political, social, and cultural institutions); W. Haywood Burns, Race in Early America, in The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique 119 (David Kairys ed., 1990) (describing the comparative powerlessness of African Americans); john a. powell, Transformative Action: A Strategy for Ending Racial Hierarchy and Achieving True Democracy in the United States, South Africa, and Brazil Part I.B.1. (forthcoming 1999 by Southern Education Foundation) (analyzing the comparative disadvantage of people of color in the United States, South Africa, and Brazil).

n23 For a detailed critique of the "intent" standard, see Barbara Flagg, "Was Blind But Now I See": White Race Consciousness and the Requirement of Discriminatory Intent, 91 Mich. L. Rev. 953 (1993); Lawrence, supra note 8.

n24 Lawrence, supra note 8, at 319-20.

n25 Id.

n26 426 U.S. 229 (1976).

n27 Id. at 256-73.

n28 Id. at 237.

n29 Id. at 246, 256-73.

n30 Id.

n31 Id. at 245 ("As an initial matter, we have difficulty understanding how a law establishing a racially neutral qualification for employment is nevertheless racially discriminatory ... .").

n32 This contextualized understanding of equality avoids the mistake of equating symmetry or rigid neutrality with equality. Substantive equality embodies the idea that treating unequally situated people the same perpetuates inequality. For a more in depth discussion of the meaning of substantive equality, see Catherine MacKinnon, Only Words 85-91 (1993); Laurence H. Tribe, American Constitutional Law 1514 (1988); Kimberle Williams Crenshaw, Race, Reform and Retrenchment: Transformation and Legitimation in Anti-Discrimination Law, 101 Harv. L. Rev. 1331, 1384 (1988). See generally Roberto Unger, False Necessity: Necessitarian Social Theory in the Service of Radical Democracy (1987).

n33 For a discussion of the flawed assumption that the status quo is neutral and natural, see Martha Minnow, Making All the Difference 49-78 (1990); John O. Calmore, Racialized Space and the Culture of Segregation: "Hewing a Stone of Hope from a Mountain of Despair," 143 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1233, 1243-44 (1995). See also U.S. v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 327 (1978) (plurality) ("We cannot ... let color blindness become myopia which masks the reality that many created 'equal' have been treated within our lifetimes as inferior both by the law and by their fellow citizens.").

n34 For a well-known example of this line of thinking in United States jurisprudence, see Village of Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Hous. Dev. Corp., 429 U.S. 252 (1977).

n35 Justin D. Cummins, Recasting Fair Share: Toward Effective Housing Law and Principled Social Policy, 14 Law & Ineq. J. 339, 341-57 (1996) (documenting the extent of discrimination with respect to the opportunity structure in the United States and discussing the social, economic, and policy implications); john a. powell, The "Racing" of American Society: Race Functioning as a Verb Before Signifiying as a Noun, 15 Law & Ineq. J. 99, 122-23 (1997) (discussing people of color's lack of access to the opportunity structure).

n36 See, e.g., Village of Arlington Heights, 429 U.S. at 252. In the United States Supreme Court's most recent cases dealing with race and discrimination, the Court has repeatedly and vociferously stated the need for proof of "particularized" discrimination before a legal remedy becomes appropriate. See, e.g., Shaw v. Hunt, 517 U.S. 899 (1996); Bush v. Vera, 517 U.S. 952 (1996); Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U.S. 200 (1995); Missouri v. Jenkins, 115 U.S. 70 (1995); Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630 (1993).

n37 Village of Arlington Heights, 429 U.S. at 252.

n38 Id. at 255.

n39 Id. at 256-57.

n40 Id. at 257-59.

n41 Id. at 257-58.

n42 Id. at 269.

n43 Id. at 269-71.

n44 Id. at 269-70.

n45 Id. (reasoning that the evidence of racism in the community in which the racially integrated affordable housing was to be built did not taint the motives underlying the defendants' opposition to the housing).

n46 See, e.g., Lawrence, supra note 8, at 339-44.

n47 Anthony Downs, New Visions for Metropolitan America 25-26 (1994) (discussing the role of race and racism in creating and maintaining segregated housing patterns); Dennis R. Judd & Todd Swanstrom, City Politics: Private Power and Public Policy 155 (1994) (describing the discriminatory real estate and lending practices as reasons for the exclusion of people of color from certain communities and types of housing); Oliver & Shapiro, supra note 22, at 8 (showing that governmental and private actors and policies have erected obstacles to access to housing and capital markets, undermining the ability of people of color to accumulate wealth and secure a better life); Reynolds Farley, Neighborhood Preferences and Aspirations Among Blacks and Whites, in Housing Markets and Residential Mobility 161, 183-85 (G. Thomas Kingsley & Margery Austin Turner eds., 1993) (determining that racism taints residential patterns and ultimately results in the discrimination against, and exclusion of, people of color).

n48 Id.

n49 See Judd & Swanstrom, supra note 47, at 212-13; Douglas S. Massey & Nancy A. Denton, American Apartheid: Segregation and the Making of the Underclass 160-61 (1993) (illustrating the ongoing discrimination against people of color); Michael H. Schill & Susan M. Wachter, The Spatial Bias of Federal Housing Law and Policy: Concentrated Poverty in Urban America, 143 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1285, 1333-35 (1995) (discussing the deleterious effects of discrimination and segregation on low-income communities of color).

n50 See Edward D. Goetz et al., Center for Urban and Regional Affairs, There Goes the Neighborhood? The Impact of Subsidized Multi-Family Housing on Urban Neighborhoods 12-15 (1996) (analyzing the impact of siting affordable housing on surrounding property values, reviewing over one dozen similar studies, and concluding that the presence of low- and moderate-income housing does not depress surrounding property values); Robert Lyons & Scott Loveridge, University of Minnesota's Department of Agriculture and Applied Economics, An Hedonic Estimation of the Effect of Federally Subsidized Housing on Nearby Residential Property Values I (1993) (showing that affordable housing units have little, if any, negative impact on the value of surrounding properties); Hugh Nourse, The Effect of Public Housing on Property Values in St. Louis, 39 Land Econ. 433, 440- 41 (1963) (revealing that the presence of low- and moderate-income housing has little effect on surrounding property values); William Rabiega et al., The Property Value Impacts of Public Housing Projects in Low and Moderate Density Residential Neighborhoods, 60 Land Econ. 174, 178 (1984) (illustrating that affordable housing does not harm the value of nearby real estate).

n51 Lawrence, supra note 8, at 369-70 (explaining the subtle, yet decisive, role racism plays in affecting intent and agency).

n52 Village of Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Hous. Dev. Corp., 429 U.S. 252, 269-70 (1977).

n53 See supra notes 18-52 and accompanying text.

n54 This principle demands that all individuals should be treated the same, regardless of their comparative position or history and regardless of context. For cogent critiques of this view of equality, see generally Neil Gotanda, A Critique of "Our Constitution is Color-Blind," 44 Stan. L. Rev. 1 (1991); john a. powell, Racial Realism or Racial Despair?, 24 Conn. L. Rev. 533 (1992).

n55 Derrick Bell, Racial Realism, 24 Conn. L. Rev. 363, 377 (1992) (criticizing equality, in its formalistic sense, as ultimately an empty concept); Gotanda, supra note 54, at 68. See also Mari J. Matsuda, Voices of America: Accent, Antidiscrimination Law, and a Jurisprudence for the Last Reconstruction, 100 Yale L.J. 1329, 1392-96 (1991).

n56 See john a. powell, An Agenda for the Post-Civil Rights Era, 20 S.F. L. Rev. 889, 904 (1995) (noting that the United States Supreme Court has adopted this perspective).

n57 For an excellent discussion of the seemingly paradoxical phenomenon of legitimating discrimination through anti-discrimination laws, see generally Roy L. Brooks, Racial Subordination Through Formal Equal Opportunity, 25 San Diego L. Rev. 879 (1988); Crenshaw, supra note 32; Alan Freeman, Racism, Rights and the Quest for Equality of Opportunity: A Critical Legal Essay, 23 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 295 (1988). In the context of analyzing Harvard Law School faculty diversity efforts, a prominent critical race theorist offers an excellent description of how the power structure makes marginal modifications to the status quo to create a "safety valve" for dissent and, ultimately, to protect and reinforce existing discriminatory arrangements: "by hiring a few token people of color - but not so many as to upset the order of things - the faculty assures itself that there is no longer an irrational, color-based barrier to the admission of blacks to the Academy. Without any earth-shattering changes in the status quo, they can promote a few people of color and then claim that things are fair and even." Derrick Bell, Confronting Authority: Reflections of an Ardent Protester 77 (1994).

n58 David Theo Goldberg, Racist Culture: Philosophy and the Politics of Meaning 198 (1993) (explaining how the anti-social behavior growing out of discrimination-induced deprivation becomes a self-serving rationale for those who discriminate to continue doing so); Robert Chang, Toward an Asian American Scholarship: Critical Race Theory, Post-Structuralism, and Narrative Space, 81 Cal. L. Rev. 1243, 1286 (1993) ("[Racial] exclusion, at a certain point, becomes so pervasive that it becomes invisible. In this way, the present-day effects of exclusion become disconnected from the past. As a consequence, the oppressed are blamed for the sins of their oppressors."). See generally, Alex Johnson, Jr., How Race and Poverty Intersect to Prevent Integration: Destabilizing Race as a Vehicle to Integrate Neighborhoods, 143 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1595 (1995); Martha Mahoney, Segregation, Whiteness, and Transformation, 143 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1659 (1995).

n59 Id.; Calmore, supra note 33. See also Johnson, supra note 58; Mahoney, supra note 58. Some commentators have even argued that racial inequality, even if not flowing directly from past discrimination, induces future discrimination. See Paul Brest, Foreword: In Defense of the Antidiscrimination Principle, 90 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 43 (1976); Charles R. Lawrence, "Justice" or "Just Us": Racism and the Role of Ideology, 35 Stan. L. Rev. 831, 849 (1983) (reviewing David L. Kirp, Just Schools: The Idea of Racial Equality in American Education (1982)).

n60 See generally Derrick Bell, Race, Racism, and American Law (1992) (illustrating the subordination of people of color and the privilege of whites achieved through legal discourse and United States jurisprudence); Goldberg, supra note 58; United States National Advisory Committee on Civil Disorders, The Kerner Report (1965) (documenting the causes and effects of racial inequality in the United States) [hereinafter Kerner Commission].

n61 John O. Calmore, Exploring Michael Omi's "Messy" Real World of Race: An Essay for "Naked People Longing to Swim Free," 15 Law & Ineq. J. 25, 53 (1997) ("the new right and neoconservative right projects have ... effectively rearticulated the meaning and significance of race in a manner that supports a societal organization and culture that ... reinforces white dominion and privilege ... a majority of the Supreme Court justices is taking its lead from these projects and is intentionally solidifying the project's gains.").

n62 See generally Sandel, supra note 2.

n63 For a good discussion of this dynamic,

- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -